This HTML version of
You might prefer to read the PDF version, or you can buy a hard copy from Amazon.
Chapter 11 Hypothesis Testing
11.1 Back to the Euro problem
In Section 4.1 I presented a problem from MacKay’s Information Theory, Inference, and Learning Algorithms:
A statistical statement appeared in “The Guardian" on Friday January 4, 2002:When spun on edge 250 times, a Belgian one-euro coin came up heads 140 times and tails 110. ‘It looks very suspicious to me,’ said Barry Blight, a statistics lecturer at the London School of Economics. ‘If the coin were unbiased, the chance of getting a result as extreme as that would be less than 7%.’But do these data give evidence that the coin is biased rather than fair?
We estimated the probability that the coin would land face up, but we didn’t really answer MacKay’s question: Do the data give evidence that the coin is biased?
In Chapter 4 I proposed that data are in favor of a hypothesis if the data are more likely under the hypothesis than under the alternative or, equivalently, if the Bayes factor is greater than 1.
In the Euro example, we have two hypotheses to consider: I’ll use F for the hypothesis that the coin is fair and B for the hypothesis that it is biased.
If the coin is fair, it is easy to compute the likelihood of the data, p(D|F). In fact, we already wrote the function that does it.
def Likelihood(self, data, hypo):
x = hypo / 100.0
head, tails = data
like = x**heads * (1-x)**tails
return like
To use it we can create a Euro suite and invoke Likelihood:
suite = Euro()
likelihood = suite.Likelihood(data, 50)
p(D|F) is 5.5 · 10−76, which doesn’t tell us much except that the probability of seeing any particular dataset is very small. It takes two likelihoods to make a ratio, so we also have to compute p(D|B).
It is not obvious how to compute the likelihood of B, because it’s not obvious what “biased” means.
One possibility is to cheat and look at the data before we define the hypothesis. In that case we would say that “biased” means that the probability of heads is 140/250.
actual_percent = 100.0 * 140 / 250
likelihood = suite.Likelihood(data, actual_percent)
This version of B I call B_cheat
; the likelihood of
b_cheat
is 34 · 10−76 and the likelihood ratio is
6.1. So we would say that the data are evidence in favor of this
version of B.
But using the data to formulate the hypothesis is obviously bogus. By that definition, any dataset would be evidence in favor of B, unless the observed percentage of heads is exactly 50%.
11.2 Making a fair comparison
To make a legitimate comparison, we have to define B without looking at the data. So let’s try a different definition. If you inspect a Belgian Euro coin, you might notice that the “heads” side is more prominent than the “tails” side. You might expect the shape to have some effect on x, but be unsure whether it makes heads more or less likely. So you might say “I think the coin is biased so that x is either 0.6 or 0.4, but I am not sure which.”
We can think of this version, which I’ll call B_two
as a hypothesis made up of two
sub-hypotheses. We can compute the likelihood for each
sub-hypothesis and then compute the average likelihood.
like40 = suite.Likelihood(data, 40)
like60 = suite.Likelihood(data, 60)
likelihood = 0.5 * like40 + 0.5 * like60
The likelihood ratio (or Bayes factor) for b_two
is 1.3, which
means the data provide weak evidence in favor of b_two
.
More generally, suppose you suspect that the coin is biased, but you
have no clue about the value of x. In that case you might build a
Suite, which I call b_uniform
, to represent sub-hypotheses from
0 to 100.
b_uniform = Euro(xrange(0, 101))
b_uniform.Remove(50)
b_uniform.Normalize()
I initialize b_uniform
with values from 0 to 100.
I removed the sub-hypothesis that x is 50%, because if
x is 50% the coin is fair, but it has almost no
effect on the result whether you remove it or not.
To compute the likelihood of
b_uniform
we compute the likelihood of each sub-hypothesis
and accumulate a weighted average.
def SuiteLikelihood(suite, data):
total = 0
for hypo, prob in suite.Items():
like = suite.Likelihood(data, hypo)
total += prob * like
return total
The likelihood ratio for b_uniform
is 0.47, which means
that the data are weak evidence against b_uniform
,
compared to F.
If you think about the computation performed by
SuiteLikelihood
, you might notice that it is similar to an
update. To refresh your memory, here’s the Update function:
def Update(self, data):
for hypo in self.Values():
like = self.Likelihood(data, hypo)
self.Mult(hypo, like)
return self.Normalize()
And here’s Normalize:
def Normalize(self):
total = self.Total()
factor = 1.0 / total
for x in self.d:
self.d[x] *= factor
return total
The return value from Normalize is the total of the
probabilities in the Suite, which is the average of the likelihoods
for the sub-hypotheses, weighted by the prior probabilities. And Update passes this value along, so instead of using SuiteLikelihood, we could compute the likelihood of
b_uniform
like this:
likelihood = b_uniform.Update(data)
11.3 The triangle prior
In Chapter 4 we also considered a triangle-shaped prior that gives higher probability to values of x near 50%. If we think of this prior as a suite of sub-hypotheses, we can compute its likelihood like this:
b_triangle = TrianglePrior()
likelihood = b_triangle.Update(data)
The likelihood ratio for b_triangle
is 0.84, compared to F, so
again we would say that the data are weak evidence against B.
The following table shows the priors we have considered, the likelihood of each, and the likelihood ratio (or Bayes factor) relative to F.
Hypothesis | Likelihood | Bayes |
× 10−76 | Factor | |
F | 5.5 | – |
B_cheat | 34 | 6.1 |
B_two | 7.4 | 1.3 |
B_uniform | 2.6 | 0.47 |
B_triangle | 4.6 | 0.84 |
Depending on which definition we choose, the data might provide evidence for or against the hypothesis that the coin is biased, but in either case it is relatively weak evidence.
In summary, we can use Bayesian hypothesis testing to compare the likelihood of F and B, but we have to do some work to specify precisely what B means. This specification depends on background information about coins and their behavior when spun, so people could reasonably disagree about the right definition.
My presentation of this example follows David MacKay’s discussion, and comes to the same conclusion. You can download the code I used in this chapter from http://thinkbayes.com/euro3.py. For more information see Section 0.3.
11.4 Discussion
The Bayes factor for B_uniform
is 0.47, which means
that the data provide evidence against this hypothesis, compared
to F. In the previous section I characterized this evidence
as “weak,” but didn’t say why.
Part of the answer is historical. Harold Jeffreys, an early proponent of Bayesian statistics, suggested a scale for interpreting Bayes factors:
Bayes | Strength |
Factor | |
1 – 3 | Barely worth mentioning |
3 – 10 | Substantial |
10 – 30 | Strong |
30 – 100 | Very strong |
> 100 | Decisive |
In the example, the Bayes factor is 0.47 in favor of B_uniform
,
so it is 2.1 in favor of F, which Jeffreys would consider “barely
worth mentioning.” Other authors have suggested variations on the
wording. To avoid arguing about adjectives, we could think about odds
instead.
If your prior odds are 1:1, and you see evidence with Bayes factor 2, your posterior odds are 2:1. In terms of probability, the data changed your degree of belief from 50% to 66%. For most real world problems, that change would be small relative to modeling errors and other sources of uncertainty.
On the other hand, if you had seen evidence with Bayes factor 100, your posterior odds would be 100:1 or more than 99%. Whether or not you agree that such evidence is “decisive,” it is certainly strong.
11.5 Exercises
What is your prior degree of belief in this kind of ESP? Do you think it is as likely to exist as not? Or are you more skeptical about it? Write down your prior odds.
Now compute the strength of the evidence it would take to convince you that ESP is at least 50% likely to exist. What Bayes factor would be needed to make you 90% sure that ESP exists?
Now suppose that you read a paper in a respectable peer-reviewed scientific journal that presents evidence with Bayes factor 1000 in favor of ESP. Would that change your mind?
If not, how do you resolve the apparent contradiction? You might find it helpful to read about David Hume’s article, “Of Miracles,” at http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Of_Miracles.